Advertisement

Responsive Advertisement

Adorno and the Categorical Imperative

Adorno and the Categorical Imperative
Given Adorno's emphasis on the particular as important in addition to the total, it is surprising that, to this point, we have only seen him examine universal concepts (such as “the particular” and “the total”) with little reference and direct relevance to the material world. Granted, the material world is lurking behind Adorno's claims, but even our interpretations of the passage that includes the phrase, “to write poetry after Auschwitz is barbaric,” were all conceptual; they might draw from the material world, but do not, in turn, give back to it by altering human behavior in it. Although no such practical element is obvious in CCS, it does appear in others of Adorno's texts, the most obvious example of which is his claim in ND that “A new categorical imperative has been imposed by Hitler upon unfree mankind: to arrange their thoughts and actions so that Auschwitz will not repeat itself, so that nothing similar will happen” (ND 365). He repeats the claim in “Education After Auschwitz”: “The premier demand upon all education is that Auschwitz not happen again” (“Education After Auschwitz” 19). In this section, I will argue that Adorno's new categorical imperative follows the themes that we have already seen in Adorno's thought, but because of its practical twist, it deals with the issues in a more personal way. My argument here follows Bernstein's argument on this topic in Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics fairly closely.

Both of these claims come at the beginnings of sections (the latter quotation is the first sentence “Education After Auschwitz”), and Adorno follows both by arguing that a justification of these claims is not only unnecessary but wrong (“an outrage” in ND [365], “monstrous” in “Education After Auschwitz” [19]). Thus, both texts employ a jarring effect similar to that of Adorno’s claim in CCS that writing poetry after Auschwitz is barbaric. Bernstein argues that this jarring nature, and the claim that justification is outrageous is a result of the physical basis for the new categorical imperative. For Bernstein, Adorno's imperative is based on physical abhorrence to Auschwitz (Bernstein 386). When we hear about Auschwitz, if we understand what happened and its implications, we cannot help but feel that it should not have been and should not be, and this abhorrence then alters the way that we understand everything else (391). Thus, it makes sense that, upon seeing in Auschwitz a totalizing objectification, Adorno finds examples of it all around him. His thought is dominated by an awareness of doom that Auschwitz did happen, that it should not happen again, but that the forces that allowed it to happen are still in place (a thought related to the interpretation that Adorno’s claim means that poetry cannot succeed at its function), and that (therefore) any individual (or communal) attempt is feeble (a thought related to the interpretation that Adorno’s claim means that poetry is self-contradictory), but still necessary (a thought related to the interpretation that Adorno’s claim emphasizes the particular over the total).

Yet, Bernstein claims that this response, because it is physical in nature, is also based on an individual experience of Auschwitz (392). Hence, Adorno's tone in the middle of the section preceding his categorical imperative in ND becomes more personal. Bernstein sees Adorno's personal experience in this section so clearly that he claims that “Adorno writes of himself in the third person although the sense of the passage is irremediably first-person” (392). In this section, Adorno talks about “the drastic guilt of him who was spared,” through which “he will be plagued by dreams such as that he is no longer living at all, that he was sent to the ovens in 1944 and his whole existence since has been imaginary, an emanation of the insane wish of a man killed twenty years earlier” (ND 363). We can see already a vast difference between the tone here and that of any of the passages in CCS. The terms are more personal (“guilt” and “dreams”), and we find an individual subject outside of his profession (“him who was spared” as opposed to “the cultural critic”). This experience, then, is personal, practical, and based in feeling, such that the understanding of Auschwitz that results from it is also personal, practical, and based in feeling, though we could not see it in CCS. Such an attitude is exemplified in Adorno's move from the question of whether writing poetry is possible to the question of whether living is possible after Auschwitz in his later writing (362-3). The question of whether one can live, as a personal question that determines our understanding of Auschwitz, is a prerequisite to the question of whether one can write poetry. 

Before we understand Auschwitz's disruption to our culture, we have to understand Auschwitz's disruption to our selves and thus to our understanding of what Auschwitz is and what culture is. This last point becomes especially interesting in ND because Adorno attributes the possibility of poetry there to its ability to give voice to suffering, just as we saw him do in “Commitment” above (p. 30-1). If suffering is also the basis of the impossibility of living after Auschwitz, then the possibility of poetry is based in the impossibility of living. Just as culture's relationship with society makes it impossible, culture's relationship with individual experience makes it possible or even necessary (as in “Liquidation of the Self”).

Bernstein goes too far, though, when he claims that the first and third person in this passage melt together (Bernstein 392). Although the experience of Auschwitz is personal, at the same time it is not a unique experience to Adorno, and Adorno expects all of those who were spared and who understand the implications of being spared (that they live in a society that committed such atrocities and could commit them again) to have responded similarly. Otherwise, Adorno's text would employ the first person and would not talk about the “categorical imperative,” a Kantian term for an imperative that results a priori from how we respond to our world.[1] Anyone, therefore, who feels physical repugnance for Auschwitz has placed the categorical imperative upon themselves. 

Thus, when (based on his conclusion that Adorno is speaking from a strictly personal experience) Bernstein claims that any event could have caused the same imperative (393, 395), he is logically correct, since there is nothing logically impossible about our feeling physical abhorrence for a fly buzzing around, but – at the same time – for Adorno, Auschwitz is an experience that cannot be equated with the buzzing of a fly. The physical abhorrence to Auschwitz is, in other words, both particular (insofar as it is a personal response) and total (insofar as it is a response that anyone who understands the implications of Auschwitz should feel), and the totality is informed by the particularity because our understanding of the implications of Auschwitz are based on Adorno's personal response to it.


[1]    For Kant, the categorical imperative results from the concept of “the law.” That a law demands that we follow it under any circumstances forces us to accept that we should act in a particular way. (See Kant's The Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals.) For Adorno, then, it would make sense that the categorical imperative results from our physical repugnance to Auschwitz. That we have felt physical repugnance forces us to accept that we should act in a particular way.